Why Animal
Experimentation Matters
This review takes its name from the title of a collection of essays
published in 2001: Why Animal Experimentation Matters: The Use
of Animals in Medical Research (Ellen Frankel Paul and Jeffrey
Paul, editors; published by the Social Philosophy and Policy Foundation
and by Transaction Publishers. Paperback edition.)
Why Animal Experimentation Matters: The Use of Animals in Medical
Research includes three essays from scientists who experiment
on animals and six essays, including the introduction, from philosophers
who defend animal experimentation and other uses of animals as well.
The essays present various justifications for using animals in medical
research, product testing, and even recreational killing (i.e. bullfights,
etc.). Discussions includes the moral value assigned to pain and
suffering in humans and nonhuman animals, the moral value assigned
to human and nonhuman lives, and the moral value assigned to human
and nonhuman actions.
All of the essayists begin with the assumption that the current
use of animals by humans is as it should be, or is overly regulated
and constrained. In various ways, they all try to justify human
domination over all other species. They do not agree as to why humans
have a right to exploit animals, but they do agree that this is
a right that humans possess.
Philosophical positions can be evaluated only by their results.
In other words, if one develops a seemingly rational and self-consistent
philosophy that results in a justification of widespread, institutionalized,
industrialized, routine evil, then the premises on which the philosophy
is based, or the arguments stemming from the premises, must be flawed.
As in mathematics, claimed solutions to philosophical problems
must be checked. Consider the elementary logic problem of the traveler
with a hen, a fox, and a bag of corn who tries to cross a river
in a boat large enough to carry only herself and one of her possessions.
A problem arises if she carries the corn across first. While she
is gone, the fox will eat the chicken. If she carries the fox across
first, then the chicken will eat the corn while she is in the boat
with the fox. A similar problem occurs as hen, fox, and corn arrive
and are left alone on the other side of the river.
The goal is to get the traveler, the corn, the hen, and the fox
across the river safely. Solutions that fail to meet this requirement
are incorrect. No degree of narrative, explanation, or justification
will suffice to overcome this requirement. Discussions about the
relative worth of the corn, the hen, and the fox may be able to
contrive speculative value-laden hierarchies and explain why it
would be justifiable to sacrifice the fox, the hen, or the corn,
but they would be incorrect solutions to the problem.
The use of animals in medical research is generally accepted to
be a problem. Proffered solutions have been varied. The federal
government’s solution to the problem has been regulation.
Solutions offered by the essays in Why Animal Experimentation
Matters: The Use of Animals in Medical Research generally rest
on speculative value-laden hierarchies or a denial that a problem
exists. Like the fox, hen, and corn problem, it should be possible
to check a proposed solution to the problem if we knew what condition
a solution should produce. In the case of the fox, hen, and corn,
a correct solution will get the traveler and her possessions safely
across the river.
The solution to the problem of harming animals in medical research
would include not harming them, no animals kept in labs, and continued
progress in health care.
The current situation demonstrates that a solution to the problem
has yet to be put into practice. The current solution, that offered
by the regulatory effort of the federal government, has resulted
in an industry that is responsible for widespread, institutionalized,
industrialized, routine evil.
How widespread is the problem?
Federal regulations require that many products be tested on animals
prior to being tested on humans or marketed for human use. All new
drugs, all new food additives, and many household and commercial
chemicals are applied to, force fed, or injected into animals. A
single commercial testing laboratory can use five hundred animals
a day.
Every major university in the country and many smaller universities
and colleges receive funding from the federal government to engage
in animal experimentation. For many schools, this funding has become
a major source of income and an economic resource they defend vigorously.
Schools, from elementary to high school, dissect animals and use
them in science classes in various ways including demonstration
and experimentation.
It is unlikely that anyone living in the United States is more
than a short distance from a facility that is related in some way
to the consumption of animals for experimental purposes.
In what sense is the problem institutionalized?
The vivisection industry is promoted through direct federal support
as mentioned above, but the industry has also become an institution
within the government itself. The National Institutes of Health
(NIH) is comprised of many scientific bodies such as the National
Cancer Institute (NCI), the National Institute of Drug Abuse (NIDA),
the National Institute of Child Health and Human Development (NICHD),
and the National Institute of Mental Health (NIMH). All of the bodies
fund vivisection directly through grants to researchers, private
companies, and public institutions. The National Center for Research
Resources (NCRR), yet another of the 27 Institutes and Centers called,
collectively, the NIH, is dedicated to providing resources to the
vivisection industry. NCRR funds the breeding of mice, rats, primates,
invertebrates, and supports the infrastructure needed to accomplish
this task.
Recently, NIH announced a name change for its eight flagship Regional
Primate Research Centers. They are now billed as National Primate
Research Centers.
Though the Department of Health and Human Service’s NIH
is the best-known example of federal institutionalization and bureaucratization
of the vivisection industry, it is not unique. The Department of
Agriculture (USDA), the Department of Defense (DOD), and the Department
of Veterans’ Affairs (VA) all maintain large industrialized
facilities dedicated to breeding and experimenting on animals. Most
cabinet level agencies are involved in vivisection to some degree.
How industrialized is vivisection?
The precise number of animals consumed in scientific use in the
U.S. is unknown. No reliable data exists on which to base an estimate,
but bits and pieces can be analyzed. The United States Department
of Agriculture (USDA) requires animal laboratories to report the
number of certain animals they use each year. These reports include
the number of dogs, cats, primates, hamsters, guinea pigs, rabbits,
“farm” animals, and “other” animals.
“Other” animals include all other mammals except purpose
bred mice and rats.
The USDA does not count purpose-bred mice or rats. Neither does
it count birds, fish, reptiles, amphibians, or invertebrates. According
to a survey conducted by the National Association for Biomedical
Research, 17 million mice were used in 1998. The number was expected
to increase by 50% within five years. The 17 million mice used in
1998 represent a small percentage of the mice killed to support
the demand for them. The escalating demand is due to the industry’s
ability to produce mutants with known genetic profiles.
The Mouse Genetics Core (MGC) provides “a cost-effective
method for generating and maintaining transgenic and chimeric mice
for the Research Community at Washington University.” MGC
explains what it takes to produce mutant mice:
In the case of transgenic mice, for each two to eight animals sent
on to a scientist to experiment on, twenty to fifty mice must be
produced and screened. Those not meeting the genetic criteria are
killed. For chimeric mice, for each two to six that are sent on
to a scientist to experiment on, twenty to forty will be born and
tested.
Thus, in the best-case scenario, eight out of twenty animals born
go on to be used. This means that the 1.7 million mutant mice produced
and sold by NIH-commissioned Jackson Laboratory in 1997 actually
represent between 4.25 million and 85 million animals. Production
of such a large number of animals requires much mechanization. Laboratory
supply catalogs and journals increasing tout entirely automated
robotic systems.
The total number of rats used annually is estimated by the industry
to about a third to a quarter of the number of mice actually used.
No estimate for the number of other unregulated animals is available,
but it must be immense. Production of many of these animals, especially
the smaller species such fruit flies and worms, is highly mechanized.
Animal production facilities have become animal factories.
Though far fewer primates are used than mice, the large primate
production and vivisection facilities are now inspected and judged
according to industry standards. The injections and blood draws
of thousands of animals daily has necessitated a factory-like ability
to manipulate animals on an assembly-line basis.
In what ways has evil become routine?
Here, evil is defined as the causing of injury, pain, or misery.
The infliction of injury is essentially synonymous with vivisection.
Essentially all laboratory research using animals inflicts injury.
These injuries come in many varieties. Many animal models of human
disease are based on the chemical or surgical creation of infirmities.
Other models are based on the infection of animals with diseases
claimed to resemble human diseases. Other models are based on illnesses
caused by inadequate nutrition. Other models are based on the psychological
wounding of animals through unnatural rearing conditions. Animal
models are created by addicting animals to narcotics or through
chronic infusions of drugs, hormones, or other chemicals. Some animals
are used to judge the toxicity of a chemical by determining the
amount needed to kill the animal. Here are few, if any, animal models
that do not entail the infliction of injury in some form.
Pain is acknowledged by the industry to be difficult to gauge in
an animal. As a result, the degree of pain experienced by animals
as a result of the U.S. vivisection industry’s activities
is under-reported. Under-reporting of pain is beneficial to the
institution and to the scientists, as doing so reduces their paper
work burden. Scientists using covered species are required to explain
ahead of time how they propose to mitigate the pain they plan to,
or inadvertently will, cause. Researchers in non-registered laboratories,
using non-covered species, are not required to do this. Research
on pain begins with the object of causing pain in the animals being
studied.
Misery in animal laboratories is ubiquitous. Stereotypical behavior
in animals held in labs is a common topic during laboratory animal
conferences. Such lab-induced behaviors include over-grooming, odd
postures, odd movements, and self-mutilation. Over-grooming can
result in nearly complete hair or feather loss. Odd postures can
include chronic shaking, chronic submissive or aggressive postures,
or standing in a particular spot for hours on end. Odd movements
can include endless pacing, spinning, looping, side-to-side swaying,
head shaking, and combinations of such behaviors. Self-mutilation
is more common in primates than other species. The industry estimates
that 10% of the monkeys in U.S. labs mutilate themselves to such
a degree that veterinary intervention is required. Such mutilations
include gnawing fingertips, arms, and tail to such a degree that
chronic wounds result. Chronic diarrhea of no known cause is chronic
in U.S. monkey labs.
The industry acknowledges the evil inherent in animal experimentation.
It is common to hear this acknowledgement in the statement that
animal research is a “necessary evil.”
This evil is routine in animal labs. It is the nature of such labs
that evil will be common.
The authors of the essays included in Why Animal Experimentation
Matters: The Use of Animals in Medical Research present moral
theories that support and promote this evil. This simple fact exposes
the authors’ philosophies as failed solutions to the problem
of evil inherent in these labs. In the remainder of this essay I
will examine the claims made by these authors and point out where
their moral theories may have gone wrong. I repeat my claim: If
one can develop a seemingly rational and self-consistent philosophy
that results in a justification of widespread, institutionalized,
industrialized, routine evil, then the premises on which the philosophy
is based, or the arguments stemming from the premises, must be flawed.
Let us look for those flaws.
“Experimental Animals in Medical History” by Kenneth
F. Kiple and Kriemhild Coneé Ornelas (pg 23-48).
Kiple and Ornelas base their support of animal research on two
claims the first one is questionable and the second, speculative.
Their first claim is that most, if not all, medical progress is
a direct result of animal experimentation. This is an old claim,
made by many defenders of the status quo. The authors cite a litany
of conditions, diseases and knowledge that they imply would have
been impossible to prevent, cure, or gain, without the use of animals.
Their propensity to link all advancements in human knowledge of
biology with the use of animals is explicit early in their essay
when they claim that prehistoric humans must have learned about
basic anatomy while butchering animals.
Undoubtedly, humans learned about the appearance, shape, and location
of human organs from seeing them in humans who had been injured,
wounded, or killed. The authors extend their logic to encompass
the claim that every scientist who happened to use animals had to
have used animals in order to have made their discoveries. They
studiously avoid discussion of the pervasive evidence that animal
models have been at least as misleading and deadly as they have
been productive.
The second claim on which the authors base their defense of animal
experimentation is that future medical progress will require the
use of animals. They state that animals will be “absolutely
indispensable” for conquering new viruses as they emerge.
They claim that “even hindering” the use of animals
in biomedical or biotechnological research is “suicidal.”
At best, these claim are speculative. At worse, they dismiss the
leading-edge technologies that are proving to be much faster and
reliable tools for the development of drugs and therapies.
[For an in-depth examination of both of the claims made by Kiple
and Ornelas, see Jean Swingle Greek and C. Ray Greek, Specious
Science: How Genetics and Evolution Reveal Why Medical Research
on Animals Harms Humans. Continuum Publishing, May 2002. Throughout
the essays in Why Animal Experimentation Matters: The Use of
Animals in Medical Research, the authors claim that animal experimentation
saves human lives. This claim is made repetitively. See Greek and
Greek for a refutation of this myth.]
Kiple and Ornelas fail to present much of a moral theory. Their
theory is simple self-interest. The interests of the animals being
consumed by the widespread, institutionalized, industrialized, routine
evil are not addressed.
“Making Choices in the Laboratory” by Adrian R.
Morrison (pg 49-77).
Adrian Morrison’s moral theory is one of default. He believes
that those who experiment on animals do so with God’s blessing.
Not surprisingly, he feels that those who oppose animal experimentation
are evil. This is rationally unassailable. Once one is convinced
that one stands on the side of God, those who criticize you must
be on the side of evil.
Such faith leaves little room for rational thought. Morrison’s
irrationality allows him to claim that he is protecting the weak
and the helpless from those who consider themselves competent to
decide the fate of others. He believes that he knows better than
the evil animal rights activists, presumably because he and the
vivisection industry are on the side of God.
Morrison’s essay is generally unremarkable except for the
fact that he himself is a vivisector. He spent years experimenting
on the brains of cats, and says that now he is relieved to be able
to experiment on rats instead. There is one part of his essay that
stands out, and that is his justification, or lack thereof, for
the line of research he chose to make his life’s work.
Morrison says that he can imagine nothing worse than to suffer
traumatic brain or spinal chord injury. He uses such injury as the
ultimate example of a need for animal research three times in his
essay. But Morrison’s research area is sleep and wakefulness.
Further, he says that he chose not to perform certain experiments
on his cats because they would have been very painful, but that
in hindsight, he now thinks that those experiments would have been
ethically acceptable after all even though newer methods have made
the methods he would have used obsolete.
Morrison’s reliance on a faith that God condones animal
experimentation has resulted in confused and meaningless claims.
His moral theory produces more questions than answers, and he fails
to plumb the depths of his God-created pain- and misery-filled world.
Most importantly, he does not address the motivations of a deity
who would countenance His creation being consumed by the widespread,
institutionalized, industrialized, routine evil called vivisection.
“Basic Research, Applied Research, Animal Ethics, and
an Animal Model of Human Amnesia” by Stuart Zola (aka Stuart
Zola-Morgan) (pg 79-92).
Stuart Zola presents no moral theory for why animal experimentation
should be condoned. One section of his essay, titled: “The
Moral Issue Regarding Animals” turns out to be only a weak
justification of his own basic research on monkeys’ brains.
Zola’s justification for his experiments comes down to the
claim that knowledge alone is an adequate reason to harm animals.
His experiments fall within the general category of “basic
research.” That is, he is not trying to cure a disease, he
is not trying to develop a new treatment, and he is not trying to
alleviate suffering. He is simply trying to determine how to induce
amnesia in monkeys through brain injury. Zola has demonstrated that
the greater the area of a monkey’s brain that is damaged,
the greater is his or her memory deficit.
Zola’s proffered justification has three parts: 1. Experiments
should be allowed if they utilize “good science.”
2. New knowledge is just cause to experiment on animals. 3. There
is no way to tell in advance whether something discovered might
someday, somehow, be of some benefit to someone.
Zola sums up his position this way: “Therefore, it might
not be reasonable to preclude the possibility of carrying out a
study simply because it has no obvious immediate relevance, either
potential or real.” He repeats this assertion on three separate
occasions in his short essay.
In answer to those who have presented cogent theories explaining
why animals should not be harmed in biomedical research, Zola says:
“For some individuals, animal research is simply not a debatable
topic. From their perspective, animals should not be used in biomedical
research under any circumstances. There is presumably no argument
or discussion that could alter this viewpoint, and this viewpoint
will not be considered further here.” Zola’s position
of authority suggests that presumptions of correctness and dismissals
of cogent argument contrary to beliefs held by him and his peers
are devices that protect some within the vivisection industry from
meaningful self-reflection. His unwillingness to think may be based
on an awareness of where thoughtful and careful analysis will lead.
Stuart Zola is the current director of the NIH Yerkes National
Primate Research Center at Emory University in Atlanta. He is responsible
for much that occurs there. Yerkes is a well-known cog in the widespread,
institutionalized, industrialized, routine evil of animal experimentation.
His assertion that animal experimentation requires only the weak
justification of providing new knowledge is a clear statement about
the true nature of the industry’s concern for those they
vivisect.
Zola’s errors are rooted in the fact that he confuses his
wish to learn about the workings of monkeys’ brains with
the right to do so. Zola has renamed Morrison’s God, Knowledge.
“The Paradigm Shift toward Animal Happiness: What It
Is, Why It Is Happening, and What It Portends for Medical Research”
by Jerrold Tannenbaum (pg 93-130).
Jerrold Tannenbaum writes about his concern for what he perceives
to be a shifting of the traditional paradigm concerning human uses
of other animals. He says that in the “traditional approach”
that “there is no ethical import in killing animals per se,”
[his emphasis.] He says that: “Our primary ethical obligation
when we use animals (in research or agriculture, for example) is
to avoid causing them ‘pain’ or more ‘pain’
than is necessary or justifiable.” He defines ‘pain’
broadly as “unpleasant mental states” such as physical
pain, suffering, stress, distress, and discomfort.
Tannenbaum goes on at length to describe the regulations that appear
to assure that the traditional approach is adhered to in laboratories.
He worries though, that effort to assure animals’ welfare
is leading to the belief that the animals have a right to be happy
when they are not being actively used. He says that: “if
research animals come to be viewed as our friends and as
worthy of happiness and happy lives as we are animal research
will stop.” His concerns appear to be rooted in a faith that
animal experimentation is the only avenue available for biomedical
research. [Again, see Greek and Greek for a complete refutation
of this myth.]
Tannenbaum appears to be lost in an inconsistent worldview, due
at least in part to an ignorance of animals that, ironically, he
feels may be part of the cause of the paradigm shift that he claims
to see. He admits that there are animals (pets) about whom we know
enough to say that they can have happy lives and enjoyments. He
also admits that it may be ethically obligatory for us to seek their
happiness. But he claims that it is not irrational to care deeply
about some animals and count them as family members, while simultaneously
consigning others, even of the same species, to experimentation.
He says that this is similar to caring about one’s immediate
family while ignoring the needs of strangers. Since biomedical research
is intended to benefit strangers, his comparison is strained.
But Tannenbaum’s faith in the status quo, or the traditional
approach, is misplaced and, as mentioned above, rests firmly on
an ignorance of animals. This is especially ironic because Tannenbaum
is a veterinarian, though this might explain his odd recognition
of the interests of pets even as he discounts those of other animals
en masse. Tannenbaum says:
Most animals in the wild spend most of their waking hours engaged
in the difficult tasks of obtaining food or avoiding predators.
It does not seem even remotely plausible to postulate that most
animals in the wild, or bred for use in research laboratories have
a need or drive to be happy or to lead a generally happy life in
the same way in which they have physiological needs to eat, drink
or eliminate.
Many species of wild animals engage in play and other social interactions
such as mutual grooming. The traditional vision of “nature,
red in tooth and claw” was formulated long before scientists
had begun making detailed observations of animals living their lives
over time. It is now recognized that many animals have recurring
and significant amounts of leisure time and engage in activities
that appear to be pursued simply for fun. This is the case for river
otters, dolphins, parrots, many primates, dogs, cats, and rats,
to name only some of the more obvious examples. Tannenbaum’s
claim that “animals in the wild spend most of their waking
hours engaged in the difficult tasks of obtaining food or avoiding
predators” is simply false.
That Tannenbaum’s “traditional approach” moral
theory is based on an ignorance of animals is further demonstrated
by his citation of work performed by his colleague at the University
of California, Davis, John Capitanio. Tannenbaum writes:
One question that has received very little attention in the animal
research literature, but is becoming a concern for some scientists,
is how providing enjoyments and satisfactions to research animals
might affect the scientific results of important experiments. Primatologist
John Capitanio has found that the survival of monkeys infected with
simian immunodeficiency virus is significantly decreased when they
are exposed to social change (for example, by being moved into paired
housing with other monkeys) either after infection or in a ninety-day
period proceeding infection.
Tannenbaum assumes, for the monkeys in question, that being moved
into paired-housing is an enjoyment or satisfaction. But it is well
recognized that pairing monkeys who have been isolated is problematic
and prone to difficulty. Injury due to aggression is common when
such pairing is done ad hoc. In such situations, enjoyment or satisfaction
do not appear to be the typical reaction of the monkeys. Capitanio
himself has been much interested in the effects of isolation rearing
in monkeys and has demonstrated a clear distain for their psychological
well-being. Tannenbaum’s citation of Capitanio’s “important”
experiments is simply an example of citing one person’s cruelty
as a justification for the cruelty of an entire industry.
Tannenbaum wonders why people are beginning to change their opinions
about the importance of the experiences of animals being held and
experimented on. He is apparently unfamiliar with, or confused about,
current knowledge and literature regarding animals’ minds.
He seems locked in an archaic ethos and confused by the changes
he sees occurring around him. Tannenbaum’s ethical theories
are erroneous because they are based on confusion and ignorance.
“Defending Animal Research: An International Perspective”
by Baruch A. Brody (pg 131-147).
Baruch A. Brody’s essay is one of only two in the book (the
other is Frey’s) to present a thoughtful examination of the
ethics underlying the use of animals in research. This is likely
due to the fact that Brody is a professor of biomedical ethics.
But moral theories can largely be placed into one of two categories:
prescriptions and apologies. Apologies attempt to justify some status
quo. Societal behaviors, or norms, develop over time, and often
do so in a relative absence of moral self-reflection. Societal norms
have emerged from traditions that are often rooted in ancient history,
and in some cases, such as the use of animals, in prehistory. Such
tradition-driven societal behaviors are unlikely to have been molded
and established through a self-reflective process. Moral theories
that present an ethical rationale for the status quo must always
be looked at with great caution and skepticism.
The belief that society has luckily developed a particularly moral
behavior involving animals is counter to the historical record of
our behavior involving other people. But this is Brody’s
implicit claim and is why he presents an apology for the current
state of affairs rather than a prescription leading to a solution
to the problem of widespread, institutionalized, industrialized,
routine evil.
In Brody’s defense though, he does admit that the U.S. regulatory
position is morally and rationally less defensible than many of
the regulatory practices in European nations. Brody classifies the
underlying moral beliefs that appear to be acting to formulate these
regulations as “lexical priority” the U.S.
position, and “discounting” the European position.
Brody says that animals have interests, and that their interests
are morally relevant to the degree that the potential harm caused
to them must be acknowledged and weighed against the benefit to
humans that their use might provide. Brody acknowledges that, in
the U.S., in any weighing of interests, that animals’ interests,
no matter how great, will always lose to humans’ interests,
no matter how small. The European system, though weighing human
interests generally greater, does not allow a trumping of any human
interests over all animal interests. The European systems “discount”
animals’ interests, but do not zero them out. Brody believes
that the European system comes closer to being a “reasonable”
system, and that the U.S. system is extreme.
As mentioned above, however, Brody does not seek to suggest a more
humane system than that already in place in some European countries.
He seeks merely to justify the general status quo and bemoans the
lack of a clear moral justification for animal experimentation within
the industry. Brody is particularly troubled by the lack of a rational
and moral principle or position explaining humans’ greater
significance. He says that this is the crucial question that must
be answered before any reasonable pro-research position can be adequately
expounded. The absence of this explanation, however, has been insufficient
for Brody to reverse his pro-vivisection position. To this degree,
like Morrison and Zola, Brody maintains his position through faith.
Brody does raise an important point that bears further consideration.
He notes that the discounting of the interests of others is a human
society-wide morally accepted behavior. He notes that we discount
the interests of strangers when weighing them against the interests
of our family. Likewise, we discount the interests of other nations
when weighing them against our own nation’s interests. To
Brody, this explains why we can morally discount the interests of
animals they are not humans, they are others.
Brody points out that there are limits to these priorities, and
that cases could be imagined wherein the interests of strangers
might actually carry more weight than our own interests. To the
degree, however, that we generally do give greater weight to the
interests of our self, immediate family, kin, or nation, Brody asks
what the difference is between such priority and other discriminations
such as racism, sexism, or, in the case of other species, speciesism.
Brody says that further philosophical study and thought is needed
to clarify this controversy. Hopefully, if human minorities were
being subjected to experimentation, Brody would speak out and perhaps
otherwise protest against such bigotry. The fact that he does not
do so now, having admitted that he cannot easily differentiate between
speciesism and other forms of immoral discrimination, makes his
position extremely weak and his conclusions and support of animal
experimentation suspect.
Baruch A. Brody is the Leon Jaworski Professor of Biomedical Ethics
and the Director of the Center of Medical Ethics and Health Policy
at the Baylor College of Medicine and Professor of Philosophy at
Rice University. Readers could assume that when he speaks and writes
regarding the opinions and positions of other philosophers that
he would be accurate. But consider this comment:
"…we have an obligation to human beings, as part of
our special obligations to members of our species, to discount animal
interests in comparison to human interests by testing new drugs
on animals first.
This defense of animal research on the ground of species solidarity
has been developed elsewhere by the British philosopher Mary Midgley,
although her emphasis seems to me to be more on psychological bonds
and less on the logical structure of the consideration of interests
in moral thought."
From this passage, a reader must infer that Mary Midgley supports
animal research. On this point Brody is wrong to a degree that would
embarrass even an aspiring scholar. One of Brody’s anti-animal
allies, Daniel C. Dennett, comes much closer to accurately portraying
Midgley’s position when he says:
"I am not known for my spirited defenses of René Descartes,
but I find I have to sympathize with an honest scientist who was
apparently the first victim of the wild misrepresentations of the
lunatic fringe of the animal rights movement. Animal rights activists
such as Peter Singer and Mary Midgley have recently helped spread
the myth that Descartes was a callous vivisector, completely indifferent
to animal suffering because of his view that animals (unlike people)
were mere automata." (“Animal Consciousness: What Matters
and Why,” in D. Dennett, Brainchildren, Essays on Designing
Minds, MIT Press and Penguin, 1998.)
Midgley is the author of sixteen books and innumerable essays and
articles. She is among the most respected of contemporary philosophers.
The odd and radically disjoint claims concerning her position made
by the anti-animalists are indicative of their struggle to grasp
the reality of other animals as intrinsically important beings.
Baruch A. Brody’s comment concerning Midgley is far off the
mark. Brody’s citation for Midgley is her Animals and
Why They Matter. I was unfamiliar with this particular Midgley
work, so took the opportunity to read it upon being told by Brody
that I had misunderstood Midgley’s position. For that, I
owe Brody a debt of gratitude; Midgley’s argument for the
need to reassess our traditional view of animals is razor sharp.
Claiming that Midgley supports vivisection, based on the position
presented in Animals and Why They Matter would be just cause
to fail an introductory philosophy class. This point, as his reluctance
to apply the results of his own reasoning to the matter of harming
animals in experimentation, suggests, again, that Brody’s
analysis and position is woefully misinformed or contrived.
Brody’s clear misrepresentation of Midgley suggests that
the editors were less than thoughtful as they put this collection
of essays together. Apparently, the criterion was simply that a
writer proclaimed that harming animals is just and reasonable. This
intellectual laziness by the editors, or perhaps bald-faced prejudice,
is evident throughout the text.
“A Darwinian View of the Issues Associated with the Use
of Animals in Biomedical Research” by Charles S. Nicoll and
Sharon M. Russell (pg 149-173.)
Charles Nicoll and Sharon Russell are cofounders of the Coalition
For Animals and Animal Research (CFAAR), which they claim is a nonprofit
educational organization. On the single-page website, http://www.swaebr.org/CFAAR/,
CFAAR says that the organization’s two goals are (1) “To
educate the public about the true nature of animal research and
animal researchers,” and (2) “To support the responsible
and humane use of animals in biomedical research.”
This is confusing. In the cofounders’ current essay, they
write that, “moral theorizing about human duties to animals
is a pointless enterprise.” Exactly why treating animals
humanely is not a moral duty to them is not addressed. Nicoll and
Russell claim that their belief is founded on Darwinian evolution.
They say: “The relationships that develop between or among
different species (e.g. symbiotic or parasitic) are a result of
evolution. Since these relationships are based in biology, it is
nonsensical to moralize about them and to advance ‘rights’
for animals or even equality among species.”
To the degree that Nicoll and Russell attempt to present a moral
theory about the human use of animals it boils down to the claim
that if any other species acts in ways that seem less than compassionate
or even cruel, then it is natural that we do so as well. The authors
attempt to root this claim in Darwinian evolution, claiming that
the exploitation of other species is natural, and therefore right.
This is the same justification used by a little boy caught doing
something wrong: Johnny did it.
Nicoll’s and Russell’s confusion is likely due to
their unholy marriage of Darwin, who they seem to misunderstand,
and two of the leading anti-animal philosophers, Carl Cohen and
Peter Carruthers. Perhaps the authors’ deference to Cohen
and Carruthers is understandable since the authors are not themselves
philosophers and Cohen and Caruthers are among the few modern philosophers
and ethicists willing to discount the interests of animals willy-nilly.
But the authors are biologists, and their confusion about Darwinian
evolution has the ring of self-interest to it. Consider the quote
from above.
They are correct that symbiotic and parasitic relationships are
a result of evolution and based in biology, but so what? Everything
we do is a result of our biology. We can read these words because
our brain has learned their meaning. Nothing we do is divorced from
our biology. What this means is that our decisions arising
from the organic processes of our brains on how we should
treat those different or weaker than ourselves, say, persons of
different ethnicity or children or people with physical impairments,
are based in our biology. It is absurd, and obviously so, to suggest
that these matters do not warrant “moralizing.” Likewise,
human relationships with other species can and do warrant moral
consideration. The authors’ claim to the contrary is simple
self-interest and self-defense speaking in place of rationality.
This warped perspective is evident throughout the essay and should
be an embarrassment to university professors professing to be biologists.
Nicoll currently vivisects animals and teaches others to vivisect
at the University of California, Berkeley, and Russell did as well
for a number of years. Neither are ethologists however, so maybe
this is why they are so confused about animal behavior. Unfortunately,
their confused notions of animals, coupled with Cohen’s and
Caruthers’ own confused notions of animal behavior, form
the foundation for a philosophical position that is little more
than a failed search for a justification of the widespread, institutionalized,
industrialized, routine evil that the authors have contributed to
in their own laboratories.
One of Nicoll’s and Russell’s claims is that there
is a propensity toward childlessness among animal rights activists.
They base this on a survey of activists who were in Washington D.C.
on June 10, 1990 for the “March for the Animals.”
Whether or not the demographic represented by the people with the
resources to travel to Washington for the occasion is typical of
those who are concerned about cruelty toward animals remains to
be seen, but 80% were reported to have had no children. The authors
suggest that this is because activists have little fondness for
children and that this lack of fondness is maladaptive in a Darwinian
sense.
The claim of maladaption is surprising in light of our burgeoning
human population. To the authors, apparently, six billion people
consuming the planet’s resources at an ever increasing rate
seems a good strategy for our long-term survival as a species. Frankly,
the authors’ naked hatred of animal rights activists has
clouded their limited ability to think.
It is hard to find a page of their essay on which their claims
do not collapse due to faulty thinking or a misstatement of fact
(Such as their claim that 25 million animals are used in biomedical
laboratories annually in the U.S. This is the industry’s
current estimate for the number of mice and rats alone.) The authors’
weaving of Caruthers and Cohen with their erroneous understanding
of animal behavior results in a confused view of nature. They write:
"As applied by Carruthers, contractualism refers to entering
into a moral understanding with another being in which both parties
agree not to harm each other or other members of their kind. In
effect then they agree to abide by moral behavior that would be
in accord with the ‘Golden Rule.’ Only rational beings
(i.e., those with the capacity to reason) who have an understanding
of the concepts of morals and rights could enter into such a contractual
agreement. …we [can]not establish such an agreement with
any nonhuman species on our planet, even those that are the most
intelligent."
Contractualism has been challenged by modern philosophers for being
too contrived. But from a behavioral point of view it is at least
understandable why such a theory emerged. When we check out at the
grocery store, we do not push to the head of the line. We act as
if there was a contract in place to which we have all agreed to
abide. But to the degree that this is natural behavior (as opposed
to behavior motivated by the fear of going to jail for assault)
it is behavior that is common throughout many animal societies.
Quite simply, animals are not constantly fighting with each other.
Many act as if they have agreed to get along.
And it is not just members of the same species that act as if they
have entered into this contract. Many mixed species groups graze
together, flock together, swim together, and socialize with each
other. Either these animals have some semblance of a concept of
moral behavior, or else, such a concept is not needed in order for
us to get along with each other. Nicoll and Russell must be nervous
when a dog walks into a room with them since they believe he or
she is unable to understand that they are not going to attack each
other.
The authors claim that the development of weapons is what led to
our ‘contractualist’ behavior. But, as mentioned above,
many animals get along with each other. They claim that this “Golden
Rule” of behavior is almost universal in human culture, but
they fail to acknowledge the internecine tribal warfare seen in
many traditional settings or the larger worldwide conflicts, or
people imprisoned for assault, rape, or murder. To the degree that
we do get along with each other, this behavior appears to be much
older than our species. It is not a human invention.
Nicoll and Russell make many errors. They state that 99.9 percent
of all the species that have existed are now extinct. (They make
this point to frighten readers into thinking that we must fight
tooth and nail to survive.) But as biologists they should know that
this is not simply because these species suddenly succumbed to some
attack. To some degree, they evolved into the species we see today.
Just as wooly mammoths are now extinct, ten million years ago there
were no American robins.
Many species have died out during cataclysmic events. Profound
climate changes, meteor impacts, and massive volcanic events have
led to many episodes of mass extinctions. The authors acknowledge
this, and admit that there is little to nothing we can do about
it at the present time short of colonizing other planets. But they
claim that there are threats to the human species that we can fight
such as insect infestations and disease. But the claim that these
problems are responsible for past extinctions is far fetched and
based on nothing other than a wish to justify animal experimentation.
The authors claim that advanced human behaviors like fire-making
and human language led to monogamy and extended childcare. But monogamy
is seen in other species as well such as geese and gibbons. Extended
childcare is seen in elephants and whales and gorillas, to name
but a few examples. The authors should know this. The authors struggle
unsuccessfully throughout their essay to paint us as saintly and
all other animal species as devilish. The claim that humans are
historically monogamous is, at best, speculative. Modern human societies
are certainly not uniformly monogamous as a visit to many parts
of Africa or Asia will disclose.
This review is too brief to catalog the myriad errors and inconsistencies
within this essay, but one point cannot be passed by. The authors
frequently defer to their moral helmsmen Carruthers and Cohen. [Cohen
demonstrated conclusively in The Animal Rights Debate (C.
Cohen and T. Regan, 2001) that he is not in possession of the basic
facts regarding animal experimentation in the U.S.] Using him as
their guide to defending speciesism, the authors state:
"Sexism and racism are not justifiable because normal men
and women of all racial and ethnic groups are, on average, intellectually
and morally equal, and their behavior can be judged against the
same moral standards. Animals do not have such equivalence with
humans. To deny rights or equal consideration on the basis of sex
or race is immoral because all normal humans, regardless of sex,
ethnicity, or race, can claim the rights and considerations that
they deserve, and they know what it means to be unjustly denied
them. No animals have these abilities. Speciesism…is a normal
kind of discrimination displayed by all social animals, but racism
and sexism are widely considered to be morally indefensible practices."
This passage is a good example of the reasoning being employed
by Nicoll and Russell throughout their essay. First, we do not judge
only “normal” men and women as morally equal. Second,
the behavior of humans from different cultures cannot always be
judged against the same moral standards, so the authors’
premise is false. Third, if not all humans are judged against the
moral standards of “normal” men and women (whatever
that might mean), why should animals be so judged? Fourth, rights
are not dependent upon the ability to claim them. Children, many
elderly people, even the poor, are often unable to claim the right
of equal consideration, yet they are entitled to it. Why should
animals be held to a higher standard? Fifth, if one kicks a dog
for no apparent reason, the dog acts as if he or she has been wronged,
thus they behave as if they do know what it means to have a basic
right such as the “Golden Rule” unjustly denied to
them. Sixth, though speciesism may be “normal” today,
this makes it no less wrong than the “normal” discriminations
of the past. Seventh, not all social animals display speciesism
as common instances of mixed species grazing, schooling,
flocking, and socializing clearly demonstrate.
As mentioned above, and as this single passage so readily demonstrates,
the errors in the current essay are extensive and relentless. This
is the level of false justification required to defend the status
quo.
“Animals: Their Right to Be Used” by H. Tristram
Engelhardt, Jr. (pg 175-195)
H. Tristram Engelhardt, Jr. explains in his essay’s first
footnote that he is an Orthodox Christian and that his real moral
guidance concerning the human use of animals comes from the covenant
between God and Noah:
"And God blessed Noah and his sons, and said unto them, Be
fruitful, and multiply, and replenish the earth. And the fear of
you and the dread of you shall be upon every beast of the earth,
and upon every fowl of the air, upon all that moveth upon the earth,
and upon all the fishes of the sea; into your hand are they delivered.
Every moving thing that liveth shall be meat for you; even as the
green herb have I given you all things."
Engalhardt believes that every animal fears and dreads humans because
God has made it so. His essay is remarkable for its demonstration
of what can happen when a person with this foundational belief attempts
to build a moral theory concerning animal use, divorced from the
moral guidance of (even) a cruel deity. This moral freefall results
in an absurd and rudderless reveling in any and all uses of animals.
In Engelhardt’s opinion, the most trivial of human interests
are more than adequate justification for any and all uses of animals.
This leads to his moral theory’s endorsement of such enjoyments
as watching animals kill each other in staged fights or animals
being tormented and killed slowly in public spectacles.
Englehardt says that the “full moral significance of animals
can be understood only with reference to their contributions to
human contemplation, delight, amusement, welfare, and culture.”
This leads to his absurd claims that animals have the “right”
to be hunted, eaten, domesticated, bred, genetically modified, skinned,
harvested, to be used as beasts of burden, to be used in circuses,
bullfights, cockfights, rodeos, to be dissected, experimented on,
used to test cosmetics, and used in any other imaginable way.
Englehardt is a member of the Center for Medical Ethics and Health
Policy at Baylor College of Medicine. He is a professor of philosophy
at Rice University. Can it be any wonder that an industry that is
responsible for widespread, institutionalized, industrialized, routine
evil has taken root with such leadership? With moral leaders such
as Englehardt deciding what can and cannot be allowed to occur in
U.S. laboratories, is there any limit to what could be allowed?
The evidence from the labs themselves demonstrates that there is
not.
“Justifying Animal Experimentation: The Starting Point”
by R.G. Frey (pg 197-214)
It seems safe to assume that the editors gave some thought to the
placement of the essays within Why Animal Experimentation Matters:
The Use of Animals in Medical Research. R. G. Frey’s
essay is the final comment.
Frey points out rightly that the common premise in every defense
of vivisection is the “argument from benefit.” This
is the simple recurring justification that animal experimentation
saves human lives. Frey, himself, accepts this as a premise for
his own position. He then notes that this justification cannot stand
on its own merits, but requires a clear explanation of why it would
be wrong to experiment on any humans but acceptable to experiment
on animals.
To the degree that Frey writes as a reasonable man, he methodically
and convincingly dismantles the answers presented to this problem
by the volume’s preceding authors. This leads him to adopt
what he calls the “quality of life view.” This view
is rational and internally consistent. He notes that any attempt
to explain or define a criteria that can be used to differentiate
humans and other animals, with respect to a rational explanation
for why we can vivisect one but not the other, will lead to an overlap
between humans and animals. In other words, there will be humans
with such low quality lives however defined that we
will have to include them in our pool of experimental subjects.
Most vivisectionists will be alarmed by Frey’s clear and
compelling reasoning.
But Frey’s support for animal experimentation is built on
a questionable foundation and weakened further by something akin
to simple bigotry. First, Frey writes: “If the use of animals
is scientific and medical research is justified, it seems reasonably
clear that it is justified by the benefits that this research confers
on humans.” Then:
"The argument from benefit is a consequentialist argument:
it maintains that the consequences of engaging in animal research
provide clear benefits to humans that offset the costs to animals
involved in the research. This is an empirical argument and so could
be refuted by showing that the benefits to research are not all
that we take them to be. This is not the place to undertake an examination
of the costs and benefits of the myriad uses that we make of animals
in science and medicine, nor am I the person to undertake such an
examination."
Apparently, if it could be shown that research using animals provided
less than a “clear benefit to humans,” much of Frey’s
subsequent argument would be false.
Based on his faith, Frey makes the claim that: “It is ironic,
to say the least, that abolitionism has received so much attention
in the media of late at the very time that scientific and medical
research seems on the threshold of revolutionary discoveries that
will greatly alleviate human suffering.” He goes on to list
the discoveries that are just over the horizon: an AIDS breakthrough,
genetically engineered animal organs for transplant, and cloning.
It is obvious that someone who acknowledges that he is unsuited
to examine “the costs and benefits of the myriad uses that
we make of animals in science and medicine” is unlikely to
be able to predict whether current research using animals is likely
to lead to “revolutionary discoveries.”
And where does Frey get his information on which to base his faith
that animal research is clearly beneficial to humans? He cites no
specific source; he says only that science and medicine wish us
to believe that there is benefit, and that the media tells us that
this research is what the public wants. This seems a weak justification
for an entire industry undeniably hurting animals on an almost unimaginable
scale.
Frey frankly ignores the evidence that animal research is less
than clearly beneficial, and is frequently even harmful to human
health. There is now ample evidence to suggest that the benefits
on which Frey bases his thesis are suspect. If, as he claims, this
essay was not the place to make a cost benefit analysis of animal
research, he should have at least cited what literature is available
on which to make such a determination. If he has not reviewed this
literature, then his thesis is little more than an unreasoned faith-based
defense of cruelty.
But Frey might indeed be willing to make claims in the absence
of evidence, as have done many bigots in the past. That Frey is
a bigot, slips through a few times in his essay, but no where more
clearly than in this statement:
It should be obvious by now why the search for distinguishing characteristics
that are very strongly cognitive, such that their use would exclude
all animals from the class of protected beings, is doomed to failure.
If such criteria were identified, the number of humans who would
fall outside the protected class seems certain to increase, depending
upon how sophisticated a set of cognitive tasks one selects as the
screening characteristics. Making the cognitive task less sophisticated,
in order to protect as many humans as possible, creates the risk
that some animals will be included within the protected class, even
as some humans fall outside it. (My emphasis.)
So, we have to assume that including any animals within the “protected
class” is simply unthinkable to Frey, no matter what moral
argument might be proffered to justify such a categorization. Frey
is more worried about placing any species of animal out of bounds
for experimentation than he is about including some humans within
such boundaries.
Frey sums up his stance:
"Some will conclude that my position vis-à-vis impaired
humans is so objectionable that my argument is tantamount to a rejection
of animal experimentation. I don’t see it that way. For me,
the crucial question is: will we decide to forego the benefits that
scientific and medical research promise? It is hard to imagine that
we will. Hence, we are faced with the problem over humans."
Sadly, Frey has completely missed the fact that medical breakthroughs
and progress have been the result of human-based research and investigation.
This leads him into an alley with only two exits: experiments on
animals or no research at all. His solution appears to be based
on a profound, and perhaps willful ignorance of medical history.
Frey’s theory remains problematic, however. Even if he finally
realizes that the benefits he imagines arising from animal experimentation
are an always distant glimmer, like a mirage of cool water beckoning
on the horizon, he will still be left with the unassailable logic
that, to the degree that we have to sacrifice someone now
humans that it must be those with a lower quality of life.
One thing is certain: Frey will always draw the line so that he
is among the protected class.
In Summary….
The essays in Why Animal Experimentation Matters: The Use of
Animals in Medical Research have uniformly failed to answer
the problem presented by vivisection, an industry that is responsible
for widespread, institutionalized, industrialized, routine evil.
A few of the essays are worth reading, nevertheless.
First and foremost, we are given some insight into the minds of
the vivisectors. Adrian R. Morrison, Stuart Zola-Morgan, Charles
S. Nicoll, and Sharon M. Russell have all spent years systematically
hurting animals. Their attempted justifications (or lack thereof)
make this volume worthwhile reading.
The essays by Baruch A. Brody and R.G. Frey give us a good idea
of the current effort to defend vivisection philosophically. These
essays demonstrate that solid resilient arguments have yet to be
presented.
The two remaining essays, by Jerrold Tannenbaum and H. Tristram
Engelhardt, Jr., are so outlandish and mean that one wonders whether
the editors included them in an effort to shift the center further
toward the cruelty end of some spectrum. They are intellectually
suspect and written by apologists with little real understanding
of the issue; they can be dismissed as filler.
Rick Bogle.
September, 2002
Home Page | Our Mission | News
What Are Primate Freedom
Tags | Order Tag
Primate Research
Centers | Resources
|